Implementing Blakely and Remedies for Structural Rules:

Today’s opinions in United States v. Booker provide an interesting example of the problem with judicial remedies for violations of structural rules — rules that require or forbid a particular relationship, but cannot compel a particular outcome. We see this most often in the context of the Equal Protection clause. The Equal Protection clause requires the structural rule of equal treatment; it blocks state actors from treating alike groups differently. But the Equal Protection clause can’t make a legislature treat everyone well. A legislature generally is free to respond to a judicial decision finding an Equal Protection violation by lowering the bar and treating everybody poorly, instead of just one group. A court can impose a structural rule of equality, but it can’t mandate a specific level of protection.

  What does this have to do with Booker? It seems to me that implementing Blakely at the federal level raised a similar problem. Blakely imposes a structural rule for how legislatures have to do sentencing, much like equal protection decisions impose structural rules on treating alike groups differently. If a sentencing scheme permits the imposition of greater punishments upon finding a set of facts, then a defendant has a jury trial right to the finding of those facts. Over the long term, this structural rule isn’t a guarantee of good treatment. Much like equal protection doesn’t necessarily mean strong protection, Blakely doesn’t mean strong Sixth Amendment jury trial rights. It just means jury trial rights that follow the structural rule of Blakely: If a sentencing scheme permits the imposition of greater punishments upon finding a set of facts, then a defendant has a jury trial right to the finding of those facts.

  In Booker, the Court had to find the initial starting point for implementing the Blakely structural rule. It’s important to realize that the issue was only the starting point; one way or another, it’s the legislature that gets to implement the Court’s structural rule, not the Court. But the various opinions of the Court reflect two basic short-term approaches to implementing a structural rule change. One is to force the legislature to raise the bar: in effect, to mandate a strong level of protection across the board. That was the approach favored by Stevens, Scalia, Thomas, and Souter: they would have compelled the current sentencing regime to add protections to defendants by keeping existing law intact but just adding jury trial guarantees to all sentencing enhancements. It’s kind of like mandating that everyone be treated well in an equal protection case; the goal would have been to use the new structural rule to bolster protections.

  Justice Breyer’s majority opinion followed a very different approach: it takes the starting point of opting out of the structural rule entirely, preserving as much of the status quo as possible. It says, in effect, that Congress would have never designed the system it did if it had known that the Court would later on impose the Blakely structural rule. Given that, the thinking goes, it’s pretty unfair to impose Blakely’s structural rule on the existing system. So rather than use Blakely to bolster protections, the Court opted to follow the Blakely structural rule by holding that the noncompliant guidelines are no longer binding in the first place. Recall the Blakely rule: If a sentencing scheme permits the imposition of greater punishments upon finding a set of facts, then a defendant has a jury trial right to the finding of those facts. Fine, Justice Breyer says: if we’re going to impose that structural rule, then we can be most true to Congressional intent by holding that nothing in the guidelines requires the imposition of greater punishment. Ergo, no need to create all these new jury trial rights that we don’t think Congress would have wanted had they been forced to implement Blakely’s structural rule.

  Blakely enthusiasts will find the Breyer opinion unsatisfying. Breyer’s opinion tries to minimize the judicially imposed revolution by finding a starting point that preserves the status quo as much as possible. If you don’t like the status quo, you won’t like what Breyer does. I suspect that is true for many Blakely enthusiasts: in my experience, many Blakely enthusiasts are more interested in Blakely as a mechanism to create stronger Sixth Amendment protections than as an asbtract structural rule. To them, reading Breyer’s opinion may trigger a reaction akin to what you might feel if you convince a court that there’s an equal protection violation, and then find yourself stuck with poor treatment all around. While the violation has been cured in a technical sense, it doesn’t really bring you the end result you had in mind.

  On the other hand, the majority’s approach seems to me a reasonable way to begin to implement a new structural rule. Breyer’s opinion declines to hold Congress to a bargain it never struck. It implements Blakely’s structural rule in a minimalist way that in the short term tries to preserve as much of the status quo as it can. In the long run, implementing Blakely is Congress’s problem; Justice Stevens’ opinion for the Court applying Blakely at the federal level means that Congress has its work cut out for it over the long term. But Justice Breyer’s opinion gives Congress some breathing room in the short term before Congress figures out what to do next.

  UPDATE: I have made a few minor corrections to the post to clean it up a bit.

Comments are closed.

Powered by WordPress. Designed by Woo Themes